Church and State, Politics and Religion
Kenneth Cauthen
The question of religion and politics is not
the same as the question of church and state. Failure to make this
distinction results in confusion.
Church and State
The problem of church and state has to do with
institutions and the spheres of action that are appropriate for
each. Here the concept of separation is valid. The government does
not appoint bishops and pastors for the churches. Churches,
meaning here all religious organizations, do not appoint
presidents, governors, and judges. No religion can be favored over
others or supported by taxes. The state has no role or authority
in defining beliefs relating to God and worship. The free exercise
of religion is to be guaranteed. The state is neutral between
particular religions and permits citizens to believe or not
believe in God and to engage or not engage in religious practices
or belong to religious organizations according to the dictates of
their conscience. There is no religious test for holding office.
We are, in this sense, a secular nation.
Nevertheless, complications exist that confound any simple notion
of religious neutrality or pure secularism in the national life.
Incarnate in our history is a kind of "civil religion" (Robert
Bellah) that finds expression in our founding documents, our
coins, speeches of presidents, the pledge of allegiance, and so
on. This "religion of the Republic" (Sidney Mead) cannot be
defined precisely and has no official status, but it has been
operative in the national life from the beginning. This "publick
theology" (Benjamin Franklin) affirms the reality of God the
Creator as the Author of certain human rights such as liberty and
equality, gives a sacred dimension to national holidays such as
the 4th of July, Memorial Day, and Thanksgiving, and defines a
peculiar American duty and destiny under the providence of God.
These beliefs are independent of any particular historic religion
or denomination, although they echo the sacred writings of Jews
and Christians. The presence of "civil religion" in our national
life does not justify the claim of some that we are a "Christian
nation." It is not grounds for promoting a "Christian" political
agenda if this means using the state to promote religious
practices in secular institutions, e. g., government-sponsored
prayer in public schools. On the other side some
secular purists are offended by even this minimal creed of “civil
religion” and long for a common life utterly devoid of any
reference to God. Recently, a California schoolgirl who defines
herself as an atheist asserts that it is wrong to require her to
recite the pledge of allegiance that contains the words "under
God." The Supreme Court has been on both sides of this
issue. Enough complexities and ambiguities of this sort
abound to frustrate any effort to find some single or simple
doctrine defining the relations between church and state or
between religion and politics. Our courts are kept busy trying to
find workable compromises least offensive to the Constitution and
most in harmony with its fundamental intent and directives. At the
same time shifting currents of political and cultural convictions
are reflected in the evolution of judicial decisions.
Thorny problems arise in two particular areas.
The first involves trying to steer between avoiding an
establishment of religion and permitting its free exercise. Prayer
in public schools is among the most contentious. Clearly
state-sponsored prayer is forbidden, but at what point does
student-initiated, voluntary prayer in connection with school
activities cross the line? Is it legitimate for parents to use
school vouchers from a state or local government to send their
children to a religious school? The government-sponsored use of
religious symbols in public places poses another set of
dilemmas. Where is the dividing line between the religious
and secular dimensions of certain Christmas symbols, for example,
Christmas trees or a creche? In 1984 the Supreme Court upheld a
city-authorized Christmas display involving a creche because it
had mainly a secular purpose. Critics noted that this
approval was made possible only by robbing the symbol of its
sacred meaning.
A second range of problems arises when
religious belief and practice conflict with secular law. In
1878 the Supreme Court forbade the Mormon custom of polygamy
because it is “an odious practice.” In 1990 the Supreme Court
ruled that members of the Native American Church did not have the
right to the sacramental use of peyote, an illegal drug.
Should an Orthodox Jew be allowed to wear a yarmulke while on duty
in the military? The Court said no. But at what point does
state interest in outlawing reprehensible practices or
merely having secular law prevail take precedence over religious
freedom to obey God? All these conflicts occur between two spheres
of authority and activity that are in principle separate but in
practice sometimes overlap.
One example of principles in tension will
illustrate the subtleties and strains in a particularly
instructive fashion. Should tax exemption be denied to schools
that practice racial discrimination? Bob Jones University
contested a ruling against it by the IRS on the basis of the Civil
Rights Act of 1964. The University maintained that its policies
were based on religious grounds and therefore should have
constitutional protection. In listening to the pros and
cons, one notes that the defenders of Bob Jones argued from the
freedom of religion side. "While we abhor what they stand for,
nevertheless spiritual freedom is so precious that we defend it
even when we are offended at the outcome. Moreover, tomorrow
society may decide it cannot tolerate dissident groups whose
values are as far above the social consensus as racial bigots are
below that line." The President of Bob Jones argued, "What we do
is out of religious conviction, and it harms no one." The critics
countered from the reprehensible social practices point of
view. "This society cannot condone and underwrite racial
discrimination." It is no wonder that religious and civic groups
lined up on both sides. The President of Bob Jones University
asked whether Jewish synagogues that segregate men and women are
to be put under the ban or whether Catholic schools and churches
that refuse to train and ordain women for the priesthood are to be
denied tax exemption. After all, he argued, we do not exclude
blacks from the college but only forbid interracial dating and
marriage, and that applies to both races. The strongest case
for Bob Jones University and Catholic Churches is that the
practices in question are both intragroup and voluntary. In
Bob Jones University v. U. S. decided on May 24, 1983,
the Supreme Court ruled that the IRS was correct in denying tax
exemption. That conclusion makes me nervous, although I appreciate
the ambiguity and complexity involved.
The complicated relationship of religion to
other human interest is illustrated in another sequence of events.
In 1990 in Employment Division v. Smith the Supreme
Court ruled that Native American religious use of peyote is not a
constitutionally protected religious right. The principle stated
by the Court was that freedom of religious expression did not take
precedence over generally applicable laws. Over 60 religious
organizations and civil liberties groups combined to form
the Coalition for the Free Exercise of Religion to fight a trend
that was weakening religious liberty.
In response to all the outrage expressed,
Congress enacted the Religious Freedom Restoration Act (1993). It
required governments to refrain from limiting religious freedom
unless they have a compelling societal reason for doing so. Under
this act a California state regulation requiring an employment
loyalty oath was successfully challenged by a group of Jehovah's
Witnesses. In Wisconsin, an Amish group successfully challenged a
state regulation which required them to mount bright orange
safety triangles on their buggies. Some cases were lost in
the early 1990's before the RFRA was passed. In Rhode Island,
Hmong families were unable to prevent autopsies being performed on
their dead relatives. They believe that the procedure eliminates
future life after death. In Maryland, a number of Catholic
teaching hospitals had their accreditation canceled because they
refused to perform abortions. Some complained that since RFRA had
been enacted, a rise was evident in requests to obtain religious
exemptions by organized hate groups and groups with a propensity
for violence. The Aryan Nations group, a branch of the Christian
Identity religion, was cited as one example.
The downfall of this legislation started with a
case that involved a Roman Catholic Church in Texas. The city of
Boerne refused to issue a construction permit to allow the church
to expand into a historical district. The church sued, and
the case made its way through the courts. Many unrelated cases had
been initiated under the RFRA by prison inmates who charged that
prison regulation of clothing, diet, and the like are violations
of their religious beliefs. On June 25, 1997 in Boerne v. Flores
the Supreme Court declared The Religious Freedom
Restoration Act unconstitutional. The majority opinion said that
Congress had overstepped its legitimate authority when it enacted
the legislation. The act set a "much higher hurdle" for government
in regulating activities of religious groups than it did for
private individuals and organizations.
Renewed efforts by groups concerned with
religious liberty led to the introduction of The Religious Liberty
Protection Act of 1998. It called again for the restoration of the
“compelling interest/least restrictive means" test when
deciding whether purportedly neutral state or local legislation
would unduly burden religious expression. After much initial
support the coalition behind this new move began to fracture. Many
conservative religious groups continued to support it, but other
organizations concerned with religious liberty and civil rights
began to oppose it. Their fear was that it would have undermined
many state and local civil rights laws. It would have created a
new defense against claims related to disability, sexual
orientation, familial, marital, and pregnancy status, and
possibly gender and religion. The contention was that the new
measure had no provision for reconciling conflicts between a
defendant's contention that religious belief motivated his or her
discriminatory act and a plaintiff's claim that state or local
statutes provided protection against such discrimination –
regardless of the defendant's motivation. So many religious
and civil rights groups withdrew support that the bill in effect
died. Note how many groups of liberal theological and political
persuasion felt caught between their commitment to religious
freedom and their devotion to civil rights for persons subjected
to religiously-motivated bigotry. For a substantial number the
latter took priority in their minds over the former.
A more focused piece of legislation was
then offered as The Religious Land Use and Institutionalized
Persons Act. This bill was carved out of the RLPA. Its two
purposes are 1. to eliminate restrictive municipal zoning
regulations that prevent churches and religious
organizations from locating in certain areas and 2. to guarantee
institutionalized persons freedom of religious expression. They
would be able to practice their religion as long as it did
not disrupt the security, discipline, or order of their prisons or
hospitals. It was embraced by both major political parties and by
organizations spanning the ideological spectrum. Because it
targets only the two issues specified, it was devoid of the
constitutional and civil rights problems that plagued its
predecessor. The measure passed both the Senate and the House on
July 27, 2000, and became available for the President to sign.
Is religion one of many activities that
deserves protection so that other interests are equally important
in the eyes of the law? Or does it deserve special consideration
so that its claims outweigh all others? If the former, our
ultimate loyalties and our relationship to God may be demeaned and
set aside for lesser values. Yet religion may be the sponsor of
what is bigoted, heinous, reprehensible, or even trivial. How can
we protect religious liberty as a precious right and at the same
time avoid its misguided, destructive, immoral, and hateful
manifestations? To put it differently, society has a set of laws
and practices regarding justice, medical practice, morality,
decency and many other things. When religious beliefs and
practices are in conflict with what society has deemed necessary
or important for the health and welfare of its citizens or to
guard their civil rights, what trumps what? How serious a breach
of religious freedom can be tolerated for the sake of making
secular law applicable to everyone? How reprehensible must an act
be to eliminate its practice in the name of freedom of religion?
Should individuals be allowed to discriminate in the name of
religion against blacks or homosexuals or unmarried persons of the
opposite sex where their own property or private prerogatives are
concerned while a public institution should not? How do we
distinguish between private and public in these cases? How are we
to weigh civil rights against freedom of religion? To shift the
focus, is religious conviction merely an example of human
subjective preference which we can change by another choice, or is
it a transcendent objective demand that claims our allegiance in a
compelling way so that we have no choice but to be obedient
to it? The Constitution specifically names freedom of religion as
a protected right. How much weight does it therefore have in
relation to conflicting claims? All of these questions are in the
foreground or background of these current controversies.
Let me touch briefly on a subject that is still
with us. It involves a proposal by President George W. Bush.
The issue of government support for faith-based human
services is full of complications, dangers, ambiguities, and
subtleties. The beauty of religiously-oriented social
ministries is the potential for dealing with people as whole
selves, i. e., giving them food for the soul as well as for the
body. But this very unity poses the problem of how it is
Constitutionally permissible for the government to enable the
providing of secular bread without funding sectarian religion. If,
on the other hand, the delivery of goods and services to the needy
is totally divorced from the religious dimension, in what
meaningful sense is it any longer faith-based, apart from merely
being sponsored by a religious group? Why shouldn’t the government
fund a church soup kitchen if all that is dispensed is soup?
Because, we say, what the church would spend on soup can now be
spent on the church bus. But maybe they would just serve
more soup. Maybe the soup itself is a witness to the faith
behind it, but if it is, is that not a sponsorship of religion?
Would the government discriminate against some religious groups?
But that is a matter of administrative practice not of
Constitutional principle. What is a religious group? What
does faith-based mean? Can we think our way through this thicket
without falling into confusion?
Religion and Politics
The problem of religion and politics defines
another set of issues. Church and state deals with the
relationship of institutions that are structurally independent of
each other. Religion and politics has to do with two spheres of
activities in the life of the same persons. Citizens who belong to
religious groups are also members of the secular society, and this
dual association generates complications. Religious beliefs have
moral and social implications, and it is appropriate for people of
faith to express these through their activities as citizens in the
political order. The fact that ethical convictions are rooted in
religious faith does not disqualify them from the political realm.
However, the question as to how they should be presented in the
public sphere is difficult, subtle, and controversial.
Ethical beliefs and social policies based on religious faith
do not have secular validity merely because they are thought by
their exponents to be authorized by their particular belief
system. A majority of the electorate must be convinced in
terms that appeal to them. Since the population is religiously
diverse, and many profess no religion at all or prefer an explicit
secular orientation, religiously-based moral and social
convictions should be expressed in terms acceptable to the widest
possible audience. Ideally, then, social policies should not be
argued for on strictly religious grounds peculiar to a particular
denomination or faith. Rather reasons should be stated in
appropriate moral, social, and political terms that have a basis
in fundamental national traditions and values. The appeal should
be to something resident in American history and culture but not
dependent for its validity on a specific religious creed, church,
faith, or tradition.
Suppose someone says, "If some of you
Christians believe that abortion is wrong, fine. Don’t have an
abortion. But don't try to impose your beliefs on the rest of us
by passing laws forbidding it." Insight and confusion are tangled
up in this statement. A few brief comments may be helpful in
clarifying this issue in the context of the problem of religion
and politics in general.
1. All attempts to get laws passed are efforts
to impose the beliefs of some on everybody. It is legitimate for
any group of people to try to get a law passed if they believe it
will promote the common good. In that sense, it is appropriate for
Christians who are so inclined to get laws passed that make
abortion illegal but not because abortion is judged to
be morally wrong by the specific religious doctrines held by them.
They should seek to ban abortion because it would be wise
and good to do so in terms of the values present in the moral and
cultural traditions of the nation. Moral arguments in favor of a
policy are legitimate, but in so far as is possible, it is better
if they are based on an appeal to public reason not on the tenets
of a specific religious faith or theology. By public reason is
meant all the ways of discovering moral truth available to all
citizens as inheritors of the general fund of principles, ends,
and norms resident in American history, traditions, and culture.
For example, the moral argument in favor of legalizing
abortions in the early stages of pregnancy depends on the
distinction between a fetus and a fully actualized person. This
distinction for purposes of the political debate involving
citizens of many different religious and secular persuasions
ideally ought not to rest on the authority of some specific
religious text, institution, or authority as such. Rather the
distinction between a potential and an actual person should be
supported by general appeals to reason and common human experience
available in principle to all thoughtful Americans. Individuals
may personally accept the full personhood of the fetus on
religious authority (the Bible, the church, the Pope, the creed of
their faith, etc.) and vote accordingly. Ideally, however, they
will seek to persuade their fellow-citizens – a majority of whom
do not belong to their group – on the basis of more general
principles and norms that reside in the culture as a whole. This
sets the terms of the debate. It in no way predetermines the
outcome.
2. Every belief that citizens try to express
politically is rooted in some philosophy or religion or some set
of assumptions about society and its well-being. They do not come
from out of nowhere. Religiously-based convictions about society
and morality are as legitimate as those that spring from
non-religious philosophies. Hence, Christians, Muslims, or Jews
may seek to get laws passed that are rooted in their religious
convictions. Such laws are appropriate as long as they have a
secular purpose and do not constitute an establishment of
religion. Whether these laws are wise or worthy of enactment must
be judged by whether they promote the common good as judged by
national values not by the fact that they are or are not rooted in
the religious faith of those who support them. A religious
foundation is neither required not forbidden. Neither secular
humanism nor religious faith is privileged in this regard.
3. Ideally and in principle, religious
believers should not seek to get laws passed on religious grounds
but because they express the values of the secular society. These
norms and goals are defined by the founding documents and cultural
traditions as they have come to be embedded in the common life.
For example, if people of faith want to crusade for universal
health coverage, e. g., they should argue for the policy not
because the Bible or the Pope authorizes it or because God wills
it but because it promotes "life, liberty, and the pursuit of
happiness" and because Congress is constitutionally permitted to
spend money to provide for the “general welfare.” Likewise,
religious groups that seek to outlaw racial or gender
discrimination should make their case on the claim that it would
be good for society as a whole not on the fact that it is
authorized by their religious faith.
4. In practical terms, however, if believers
feel that distinguishing between the religious basis and the
political implications of their faith is an intolerable splitting
of a unitary set of beliefs, then let them act accordingly.
If people actually convince other voters to support
legislation because the Bible, the Pope, Buddhist teachings, the
Koran, or church doctrine mandates it, not much can be done about
it except to make an effort to persuade them that there is a
better way. We cannot determine or control the reasons why people
vote or support the policies they do or prevent them from
convincing others to do the same. In the voting booth citizens are
a law unto themselves. They can vote for whatever or whoever they
want for any reason that motivates them. It is pointless to demand
purity of principle on this matter. Voters act out of prejudice,
self-interest, racial identity, ignorance, and for all sorts of
other good and bad reasons, including their religious beliefs,
philosophical commitments, and a devotion to justice based on
American principles. Let us be realists about the matter.
Democracy is an untidy, often messy, matter. The people can
do what they want restrained only by Constitutional mandates. But
it is better when acting politically in the public arena for
believers to translate religiously-based beliefs into the
traditions, language, and values of the secular order. This is
called for as a matter of principle. It is advisable pragmatically
as well, since the tying of policy or voting explicitly to the
tenets of a particular religion, denomination, or sect may
repel large number of voters and hinder rather than further
the cause.
5. Hence, a two-sided critique is
required. Against those who explicitly base political
policies on the beliefs of a particular religion, we must insist
that our government does not rest on principles peculiar to one
subgroup. In this sense, we are a secular state. Hence, the
political and ethical implications of faith should be framed in
terms of the values embodied in our national history and
traditions. Against some secular zealots, we must insist that
religious people have as much right to express the social and
ethical consequences of their faith in political terms as they
have to express their non-religious or atheist philosophies. The
problem is that many religious people and secularists simply
identify their outlook with "the American way" and are unable or
unwilling to distinguish between an underlying orientation
(religious faith or secular philosophy) and its social and
political manifestations. Once again the presence of "civil
religion" in our history complicates the notion of an absolutely
secular state. Even so, the "religion of the Republic" gives
little specific ethical guidance beyond support of broadly-defined
principles of justice, liberty, individual rights, equality, and
the like. These ideals are so general and abstract that they can
usually be invoked by parties on every side of issues when it
comes to the specifics of social policy. In this connection, let
us recognize that the American tradition is subject to revision in
the light of experience and deeper insight. This occurred in the
abolition of slavery, the granting of full citizenship to women,
and the outlawing of segregation. All of these progressive moves
could call upon something fundamental in the national
creed that led to positive change. Novel possibilities can
be introduced by constitutional amendment and cultural
transformation.
6. Churches must determine on the basis of
their polity and doctrine whether it is legitimate or wise for a
church official, congregation, or denominational body to endorse a
particular policy or candidate. Hazards abound in doing so. It may
bind religious faith injudiciously to a particular or
controversial political program, and it may run the risk of
splitting the congregation or the denomination. The state,
however, must determine whether partisan political activities
engaged in officially by religious institutions jeopardize their
tax exemption or the income tax deduction for gifts to them, since
it then becomes a matter of church and state.
Working out the relations between church and
state and between religion and politics requires all the wisdom we
can summon. But it will help if we remember that they are not the
same. In both cases, we should be prepared to deal with
complexities, ambiguities, and overlapping realms in which
practical discernment must find workable principles to guide us
that are as compatible with fundamental Constitutional imperatives
as human reason can devise. Those who look for absolutely clear
prescriptions requiring no delicate balancing acts or imprecise
lines of demarcation between what is permissible and what is not
are doomed to perpetual frustration. Or they may be tempted to
resort to desperate efforts to find simplicity and purity of
doctrine by suppressing legitimate but complicating elements in
the total ensemble of historical principles and practices that
govern the nation.